Modes
of Production and Development
by HUGHO DEOGRATIUS
Webster (2004; 2002) and Garnham (2004a) have
accused Castells of technological determinism. Castells distinguishes between
the mode of production – which determines how production surpluses are
distributed – and the mode of development, which drives productivity and
thereby determines the amount of surplus production. The mode of development is
technological: according to Castells, the industrial mode of development
centered on energy; since the oil shock and stagflation of the 1970s capitalism
has seized upon informationalism to produce growth. However, he does not
believe that capitalism created the informational mode of development as a
solution to this challenge, instead tracing it to “the autonomous dynamics of
technological discovery and diffusion” (2000b, p. 59).
The theoretical problem
raised by Webster is the relative autonomy of the mode of development. The mode
of development influences social relations, but is not determined by capitalism
and, according to Castells, may survive it: “the new economy . . . may well
outlast the mode of production where it was born” (Castells, 2000a, p. 11). For
Webster, this implies that the mode of development follows its own
technological logic, is “in key respects, beyond the reach of politics” (2004,
p. 17), and therefore despite Castells' protestations to the contrary, his
theoretical basis – like that of Bell – is technologically determinist.
Garnham's (2004a)
criticism centers on productivity. He asks whether what he calls the
“thermodynamic” model of productivity, based on inputs and outputs of energy,
can be applied to information, which he suggests is non-entropic2. Castells claims that
the network economy relies on productivity increases made possible by
information technology. But, says Garnham, there is little evidence of such
productivity increases. Furthermore, he says, the “lack of a stable calculable
relationship between the value of outputs . . . lies behind the historical
difficulties in commodifying information” (Garnham, 2004b, p. 191). In other
words, even if information output is increasing productivity, this activity is
difficult for capitalists to measure and commodify, therefore it is difficult
to integrate into a capitalist economy.
Alternatively, Garnham
(2004a) says, productivity can be examined in terms of consumption and
investment and the relations of production. Here, both he and Webster criticize
the relatively autonomous role of the mode of development, emphasizing instead
determining role of the mode of production. Technology is put to work at the
behest of capital: “the informational mode of development is developed for and
put at the service of a set of property relations and the goal of accumulation,
not vice versa” (Garnham, 2004a, p. 174).
Capital and Labor
This downplaying of the role of capital also applies to Castells
suggestion that much of the power of capital has been appropriated by
informational (self-programmable) labor, particularly those actors who are at
the juncture of different networks (Castells, 2000a, p. 16). As Webster (2002,
p. 114) points out, this is very similar to the concept of a meritocracy, in
which individuals have power in proportion to their knowledge, skills, or the
value of their labor. This hierarchy of power therefore results, in Webster's
words (p. 115), from “a 'natural' form of inequality that is supra-social,
although of inordinate social consequence”. Again, the informational mode of
development appears to be autonomous of – and in fact supersedes – the
capitalist material base. A meritocratic model, of course, sidesteps the social
and historical process – affected by factors such as wealth, education, and
social relationships – by which labor is created: of how individual workers come
to be self-programmable, generic, or irrelevant.
The problem with informational labor is more
involved, however, for – as with other theories of the information society
(Webster, 2002, pp. 115-119), it is a slippery concept to define. Castells
includes such a wide diversity of tasks under the rubric of informational labor
that it is difficult to accept the interests and values of these workers as a
group. Webster provides the examples of journalists, stockbrokers, and
surgeons. The relations between these occupations and the information they deal
with is anything but consistent, and the group as a whole anything but
homogeneous. (Is it level of education? communication? influence?) In fact, it
seems that the other groups he mentions – commodity labor, surplus labor, etc.
are far more homogeneous – in their work and in their common interests – than
is informational labor.
Castells also claims that the information age is
still a capitalist age (although he suggests the informational mode of
development could survive the end of capitalism), but it is post-capitalist. In
his model, capitalists are no longer the ruling class: their power has been
usurped by the networks. The true logic of the system is the logic of the
networks. But this is not new. Marx wrote (quoted in Garnham, 2001, p. 240):
The function fulfilled by the capitalist is no more than the
function of capital – viz. the valorization of value by absorbing living labor
– executed consciously and willingly. The
capitalist functions only as personified capital, capital as a person, just as
the worker is no more than labor personified.
Garnham's comment (2001, p. 240-1) is that “a given person or
group can only be described as capitalist in those moments when s/he or they
are acting in conscious and willed accord with the logic of capital
accumulation.” Again, as both Garnham and Webster explain, the capitalists
remain in control. The propertied class has better access to education, and its
members are dominant in the top managerial positions which Castells claims are
in control of the networks (Webster, 2002, p. 118).
First, the familiarity of Castells' analysis, and the connections
he draws between the disparate phenomena and factors he examines, is valuable
(here I have looked at the forces dissolving the sovereignty of the nation
state).
Webster and Garnham present credible critiques
of Castells' concept of an information age. The network society is more
convincingly a development of industrial society than an entirely new
construct. Capitalism is still the economic basis for society; the
manifestation of capitalism's power in faceless networks is a phenomenon going
back to Marx's original critique of the system in the 19th century. Meanwhile,
the social changes wrought by information technology are not yet on the same
scale as the intense period of upheaval that corresponded to the technologies whose
effects were greatest in the first half of the 20th century, including the oil
industry, the automobile, the aeroplane, electrification, the telephone, and
nuclear physics. These criticisms affect not only the question of whether we
are entering a new age, but also some of Castells' theoretical foundations.
Garnham's (2004a) wrote his criticism of
Castells' treatment of productivity in 1998. The argument has since been
weakened by more recent studies of the matter which have found evidence for
significant productivity growth arising from the adoption of information
technology. For example, Stiroh (2002) claims that annual productivity growth
for the nonfarm business sector averaged 1.3% between 1973 and 1995, but the
average rate has increased to 2.5% between 1995 and 2000. He credits this
increase to information technology.
Castells does seem to be of two minds about the
role of technology. On one hand, he describes it as enabling rather than
determining: “The internationalization of the economy is only possible because
of information technology. It is not information technology which pushes the
process.” (1990, p. 9). His (2001) recounting of the history of the Internet
also shows how that technology is a product of social forces, themselves shaped
by the context of the capitalist society in which they were embedded. On the
other hand, Garnham and Webster are correct that Castells seems to be elevating
technology to a priviledged topic of analysis. In the context of a wider
examination of society and the relations of production, his claims for the
epochal impact of information technology seem suspect. However, I find that
accusations of technological determinism go to far. Current theories of the
social construction of technology do not reject technological determinism out
of hand; theories of the social shaping and co-production of technology (e.g.
Jasanoff, 2004; Mackenzie & Wajcman, 1999), for example, reject the binay
distinction between technological and social determination, and instead examine
how society and technology to shape each other.to
No comments:
Post a Comment